Grammar
Tenses
Present
Present Simple
Present Continuous
Present Perfect
Present Perfect Continuous
Past
Past Continuous
Past Perfect
Past Perfect Continuous
Past Simple
Future
Future Simple
Future Continuous
Future Perfect
Future Perfect Continuous
Passive and Active
Parts Of Speech
Nouns
Countable and uncountable nouns
Verbal nouns
Singular and Plural nouns
Proper nouns
Nouns gender
Nouns definition
Concrete nouns
Abstract nouns
Common nouns
Collective nouns
Definition Of Nouns
Verbs
Stative and dynamic verbs
Finite and nonfinite verbs
To be verbs
Transitive and intransitive verbs
Auxiliary verbs
Modal verbs
Regular and irregular verbs
Action verbs
Adverbs
Relative adverbs
Interrogative adverbs
Adverbs of time
Adverbs of place
Adverbs of reason
Adverbs of quantity
Adverbs of manner
Adverbs of frequency
Adverbs of affirmation
Adjectives
Quantitative adjective
Proper adjective
Possessive adjective
Numeral adjective
Interrogative adjective
Distributive adjective
Descriptive adjective
Demonstrative adjective
Pronouns
Subject pronoun
Relative pronoun
Reflexive pronoun
Reciprocal pronoun
Possessive pronoun
Personal pronoun
Interrogative pronoun
Indefinite pronoun
Emphatic pronoun
Distributive pronoun
Demonstrative pronoun
Pre Position
Preposition by function
Time preposition
Reason preposition
Possession preposition
Place preposition
Phrases preposition
Origin preposition
Measure preposition
Direction preposition
Contrast preposition
Agent preposition
Preposition by construction
Simple preposition
Phrase preposition
Double preposition
Compound preposition
Conjunctions
Subordinating conjunction
Correlative conjunction
Coordinating conjunction
Conjunctive adverbs
Interjections
Express calling interjection
Grammar Rules
Preference
Requests and offers
wishes
Be used to
Some and any
Could have done
Describing people
Giving advices
Possession
Comparative and superlative
Giving Reason
Making Suggestions
Apologizing
Forming questions
Since and for
Directions
Obligation
Adverbials
invitation
Articles
Imaginary condition
Zero conditional
First conditional
Second conditional
Third conditional
Reported speech
Linguistics
Phonetics
Phonology
Semantics
Pragmatics
Linguistics fields
Syntax
Morphology
Semantics
pragmatics
History
Writing
Grammar
Phonetics and Phonology
Reading Comprehension
Elementary
Intermediate
Advanced
Case structure
المؤلف:
CHARLES J. FILLMORE
المصدر:
Semantics AN INTERDISCIPLINARY READER IN PHILOSOPHY, LINGUISTICS AND PSYCHOLOGY
الجزء والصفحة:
376-22
2024-08-12
760
I identified the separate arguments associated with the verb rob by referring to their roles as ‘culprit’, ‘loser’, and ‘loot’; in a similar way, I might have identified the three arguments associated with the verb criticize as ‘critic’, ‘offender’, and ‘offense’. It seems to me, however, that this sort of detail is unnecessary, and that what we need are abstractions from these specific role descriptions, abstractions which will allow us to recognize that certain elementary role notions recur in many situations, and which will allow us to acknowledge that differences in detail between partly similar roles are due to differences in the meanings of the associated verbs. Thus we can identify the culprit of rob and the critic of criticize with the more abstract role of Agent, and interpret the term Agent as referring, wherever it occurs, as the animate instigator of events referred to by the associated verb. Although there are many substantive difficulties in determining the role structure of given expressions, in general it seems to me that for the predicates provided in natural languages, the roles that their arguments play are taken from an inventory of role types fixed by grammatical theory. Since the most readily available terms for these roles are found in the literature of case theory, I have taken to referring to the roles as case relationships, or simple cases. The combination of cases that might be associated with a given predicate is the case structure of that predicate.
In addition to the apparently quite complex collection of complements that identify the limits and extents in space and time that are required by verbs of motion, location, duration, etc., the case notions that are most relevant to the subclassification of verb types include the following:
Agent (A), the instigator of the event
Counter-Agent (C), the force or resistance against which the action is carried out
Object (O), the entity that moves or changes or whose position or existence is in consideration
Result (R), the entity that comes into existence as a result of the action
Instrument (I), the stimulus or immediate physical cause of an event
Source (S), the place from which something moves
Goal (G), the place to which something moves
Experiencer (E), the entity which receives or accepts or experiences or undergoes the effect of an action (earlier called by me ‘ Dative ’).
It appears that there is sometimes a one-many relationship between an argument to a predicate and the roles that are associated with it. This can be phrased by saying either that some arguments simultaneously serve in more than one role, or that in some situations the arguments in different roles must (or may) be identical.
Thus verbs like rise and move can be used intransitively, that is with one noun-phrase complement; the complement may refer just to the thing which is moving upward, or it may simultaneously refer to the being responsible for such motion. Thus in speaking simply of the upward motion of smoke we can say (30):
(30) The smoke rose
and in speaking of John’s getting up on his own power, we can say (31):
(31) John rose.
The case structure of rise, then, might be represented diagrammatically as <32):
The fact that there are two case lines connecting rise with its one argument, and that the line labelled A has its case label in parentheses, reflect the fact that the argument can serve in just one of these roles (O) or simultaneously in both (A and O). Rise differs from arise in the optionality of A; it differs from ascend in having an ‘A’ line at all, and they all differ from lift in that the latter requires two arguments.1 Thus (33)-(35):
Frequently a linguistically codable event is one which in fact allows more than one individual to be actively or agentively involved. In any given linguistic expression of such an event, however, the Agent role can only be associated with one of these. In such pairs as buy and sell or teach and learn we have a Source (of goods or knowledge) and a Goal. When the Source is simultaneously the Agent, one uses sell and teach; when the Goal is simultaneously the Agent, we use buy and learn.
It is not true, in other words, that buy and sell, teach and learn are simply synonymous verbs that differ from each other in the order in which the arguments are mentioned.2 There is synonomy in the basic meanings of the verbs (as descriptions of events), but a fact that might be overlooked is that each of these verbs emphasizes the contribution to the event of one of the participants. Since the roles are different, this difference is reflected in the ways in which the actions of different participants in the same event can be qualified. Thus we can say (36):
(36) He bought it with silver money
but not (37):
(37) *He sold it with silver money.
Similarly, the adverbs in (38) and (39) do not further describe the activity as a whole, but only one person’s end of it :
(38) He sells eggs very skilfully.
(39) He buys eggs very skilfully.
1 In truth, however, lift also requires conceptually the notion of Instrument. That is, lifting requires the use of something (perhaps the Agent’s hand) to make something go up. It is conceivable that the basic case structures of arise and lift are identical, with grammatical requirements on identity and deletion accounting for their differences. Thus the two are shown in (i) and (ii):
For arise, however, it is required that x = y = z, and hence only one noun will show up. The meaning expressed by John arose is that John willed his getting up, that he used his own body (i.e., its muscles) in getting up, and that it was his body that rose. For lift, however, there may be identities between x and z, resulting in a sentence like John lifted himself, or there may be identities between y and z, resulting in a sentence like John lifted his finger. Rise, then, must be described as (iii):
where the identity requirements of arise obtain just in case x and y are present.
2 This has, of course, been suggested in a great many writings on semantic theory; most recently, perhaps, in the exchanges between J. F. Staal and Yehoshua Bar-Hillel in Foundations of Language, 1967 and 1968.