Grammar
Tenses
Present
Present Simple
Present Continuous
Present Perfect
Present Perfect Continuous
Past
Past Continuous
Past Perfect
Past Perfect Continuous
Past Simple
Future
Future Simple
Future Continuous
Future Perfect
Future Perfect Continuous
Passive and Active
Parts Of Speech
Nouns
Countable and uncountable nouns
Verbal nouns
Singular and Plural nouns
Proper nouns
Nouns gender
Nouns definition
Concrete nouns
Abstract nouns
Common nouns
Collective nouns
Definition Of Nouns
Verbs
Stative and dynamic verbs
Finite and nonfinite verbs
To be verbs
Transitive and intransitive verbs
Auxiliary verbs
Modal verbs
Regular and irregular verbs
Action verbs
Adverbs
Relative adverbs
Interrogative adverbs
Adverbs of time
Adverbs of place
Adverbs of reason
Adverbs of quantity
Adverbs of manner
Adverbs of frequency
Adverbs of affirmation
Adjectives
Quantitative adjective
Proper adjective
Possessive adjective
Numeral adjective
Interrogative adjective
Distributive adjective
Descriptive adjective
Demonstrative adjective
Pronouns
Subject pronoun
Relative pronoun
Reflexive pronoun
Reciprocal pronoun
Possessive pronoun
Personal pronoun
Interrogative pronoun
Indefinite pronoun
Emphatic pronoun
Distributive pronoun
Demonstrative pronoun
Pre Position
Preposition by function
Time preposition
Reason preposition
Possession preposition
Place preposition
Phrases preposition
Origin preposition
Measure preposition
Direction preposition
Contrast preposition
Agent preposition
Preposition by construction
Simple preposition
Phrase preposition
Double preposition
Compound preposition
Conjunctions
Subordinating conjunction
Correlative conjunction
Coordinating conjunction
Conjunctive adverbs
Interjections
Express calling interjection
Grammar Rules
Preference
Requests and offers
wishes
Be used to
Some and any
Could have done
Describing people
Giving advices
Possession
Comparative and superlative
Giving Reason
Making Suggestions
Apologizing
Forming questions
Since and for
Directions
Obligation
Adverbials
invitation
Articles
Imaginary condition
Zero conditional
First conditional
Second conditional
Third conditional
Reported speech
Linguistics
Phonetics
Phonology
Semantics
Pragmatics
Linguistics fields
Syntax
Morphology
Semantics
pragmatics
History
Writing
Grammar
Phonetics and Phonology
Reading Comprehension
Elementary
Intermediate
Advanced
Paths vs. selection restrictions
المؤلف:
URIEL WEINREICH
المصدر:
Semantics AN INTERDISCIPLINARY READER IN PHILOSOPHY, LINGUISTICS AND PSYCHOLOGY
الجزء والصفحة:
318-18
2024-08-07
678
KF provides that to the terminal element of a path there shall be affixed a string consisting of syntactic or semantic markers, or both. The function of this string is to represent conditions on the non-anomalous employment of the word in the meaning represented by that path. For example, the suffix ((Aesthetic Object)) at the end of one of the paths for colorful would indicate that the adjective, in the sense corresponding to that path, is applicable as a modifier without anomaly only to head nouns which contain the marker (Aesthetic Object) in their paths.
This part of KF, too, is fraught with apparently insuperable difficulties. Consider the case of the adjective pretty. It seems to be applicable to inanimates and, among animates, to females. If its selection restriction were stated as ((Inanimate) V (Animate)-f (Female)),b the normality of pretty girls as well as the anomaly of pretty boys would be accounted for, since girls has the marker (Female) in its path, while boys does not. But we can also say pretty children without anomaly, even though child does not contain (Female) in its path; in fact, English speakers will refer the sex of the neutral children from the attribute, and a theory concerned with ‘ the interpretative ability of speakers ’ must account for this inference. One way of doing so would be to reformulate the selection restriction more carefully, e.g. as ((Inanimate) v ~ (Male)), to be read: predicable of Inanimates and not predicable of Males. This would explain why pretty children is not anomalous, but would not yet show how we infer that the children are girls, since the projection rules only check on whether the conditions of selection restriction are satisfied, but transfer no information from the angle-bracketed position to the amalgamated path. Moreover, the case of Female = ~ Male is probably quite atypically favorable in that we have two values of a feature dichotomizing a large domain in a relevant way. If, on the other hand, addled were to be marked in its selection as restricted to eggs and brains, the restriction would be unlikely to be statable in terms of legitimate markers (without distinguishers); and again we would lack an explanation of how we know that in It’s addled, the referent of it is an egg or a brain. Here a restriction in terms of negatives, e.g. (~ [( ~ Eggs) V ( ~ Brains)]), would be intolerably ad-hoc.
Two alternatives may be considered. One would be to regard ‘Constructability with Z’ as an intrinsic feature of a dictionary entry W (i.e. of the ‘path’ of W), and not as a statement external to the path. The other is to adopt a more powerful conception of the semantic interpretation process, in which features of selection restriction of a word Z would be transferred into the path of another word, W, when it is constructed with Z. This is the solution adopted by Katz and Postal (1964: 83) for a special purpose [(c)], and it is the general solution [pp. 429 ff.]. But with respect to KF, it seems safe to conclude that the distinction between paths and selection restrictions is an untenable as its other specifications of the format of dictionary entries.
1 If Female necessarily implies Animate, the notation could of course be simplified; see Katz and Postal (1964 16 ff.). On the theoretical implications of such simplifications.