1

المرجع الالكتروني للمعلوماتية

Grammar

Tenses

Present

Present Simple

Present Continuous

Present Perfect

Present Perfect Continuous

Past

Past Continuous

Past Perfect

Past Perfect Continuous

Past Simple

Future

Future Simple

Future Continuous

Future Perfect

Future Perfect Continuous

Passive and Active

Parts Of Speech

Nouns

Countable and uncountable nouns

Verbal nouns

Singular and Plural nouns

Proper nouns

Nouns gender

Nouns definition

Concrete nouns

Abstract nouns

Common nouns

Collective nouns

Definition Of Nouns

Verbs

Stative and dynamic verbs

Finite and nonfinite verbs

To be verbs

Transitive and intransitive verbs

Auxiliary verbs

Modal verbs

Regular and irregular verbs

Action verbs

Adverbs

Relative adverbs

Interrogative adverbs

Adverbs of time

Adverbs of place

Adverbs of reason

Adverbs of quantity

Adverbs of manner

Adverbs of frequency

Adverbs of affirmation

Adjectives

Quantitative adjective

Proper adjective

Possessive adjective

Numeral adjective

Interrogative adjective

Distributive adjective

Descriptive adjective

Demonstrative adjective

Pronouns

Subject pronoun

Relative pronoun

Reflexive pronoun

Reciprocal pronoun

Possessive pronoun

Personal pronoun

Interrogative pronoun

Indefinite pronoun

Emphatic pronoun

Distributive pronoun

Demonstrative pronoun

Pre Position

Preposition by function

Time preposition

Reason preposition

Possession preposition

Place preposition

Phrases preposition

Origin preposition

Measure preposition

Direction preposition

Contrast preposition

Agent preposition

Preposition by construction

Simple preposition

Phrase preposition

Double preposition

Compound preposition

Conjunctions

Subordinating conjunction

Correlative conjunction

Coordinating conjunction

Conjunctive adverbs

Interjections

Express calling interjection

Grammar Rules

Preference

Requests and offers

wishes

Be used to

Some and any

Could have done

Describing people

Giving advices

Possession

Comparative and superlative

Giving Reason

Making Suggestions

Apologizing

Forming questions

Since and for

Directions

Obligation

Adverbials

invitation

Articles

Imaginary condition

Zero conditional

First conditional

Second conditional

Third conditional

Reported speech

Linguistics

Phonetics

Phonology

Semantics

Pragmatics

Linguistics fields

Syntax

Morphology

Semantics

pragmatics

History

Writing

Grammar

Phonetics and Phonology

Reading Comprehension

Elementary

Intermediate

Advanced

English Language : Linguistics : Semantics :

The lexicon and lexemes

المؤلف:  David Hornsby

المصدر:  Linguistics A complete introduction

الجزء والصفحة:  179-9

2023-12-25

710

The lexicon and lexemes

The lexicon is the mental word bank in which we store lexemes, together with their form, meaning, syntactic properties and any specific features not predictable by grammatical rule.

 

Lexemes may consist of single words, or full phrases where the meaning cannot be reduced to that of its component parts. For example, the colloquial expression to kick the bucket may be viewed as a phrasal lexeme or idiom by virtue of the fact that its meaning cannot be reduced to that of its component parts – taken together, this idiom means ‘to die’.

 

What do we mean by ‘meaning’? Philosophers and linguists agree that the concept is extraordinarily difficult to pin down:

The statement of meanings is therefore the weak point in language study, and will remain so until human knowledge advances very far beyond its present state.

 

Nearly eight decades later, Paul Elbourne seems equally pessimistic:

Despite 2,400 years or so of trying, it is unclear that anyone has ever come up with an adequate definition of any word whatsoever, even the simplest.

 

There are a number of reasons why meaning seems less clearly structured and less susceptible to scientific investigation than other areas of language. Firstly, Bloomfield claimed that our knowledge of the world was quite simply deficient, and not readily susceptible to the scientific analysis he craved:

Actually our knowledge of the world in which we live is so imperfect that we can rarely make accurate statements about the meaning of a speech-form. The situations (A) which lead to an utterance, and the hearer's responses (C), include many things that have not been mastered by science.

 

He also notes the very rough-and-ready way in which meanings are often learned. In some cases a definition will work, but in other cases it proves impractical. Rather than attempt to define, say, the word apple to a child, for example, we are likely simply to reach for an apple, show it to the child and hope that he/ she can extrapolate from that example what all apples have in common and, more importantly, what distinguishes them from pears, grapes, plums and so on. This is often the only way to explain word meanings – young children cannot after all reach for the Oxford English Dictionary or equivalent for their definitions – and generally it seems to work.

 

But if meanings are often acquired by little more than supported guesswork, how can we be sure that the meaning of a given lexeme as stored by one individual is identical to that of another? The short, and easy, answer to that question is that if our internalized meanings were radically different, then communication would be impossible: I might be talking perhaps about ‘soccer’ and imagining a game involving 22 players and a round ball, while another person would hear that term and understand what I mean by ‘blue cheese’, and yet another would access my meaning of ‘saucepan’. That clearly does not happen, as any attempt to communicate ideas would be futile. But we cannot be sure that our internalized meanings correspond exactly: is my definition of cup the same as yours, for example? At what point does cup become mug for you, and is that point the same for me?

 

For some philosophers, notably Wittgenstein, the meaning of any word eludes abstract definition and is entirely dependent on its use. It is therefore constantly modified and reshaped by its users. The word colour, for example, has a very different meaning for a painter and a snooker player: for the latter it contrasts with red and includes black, but not white, whereas no such restrictions apply for the former. In Part I of his Philosophical Investigations (1953), Wittgenstein argues that any attempt to find a common meaning for the word game in all its uses ultimately ends in failure. He observes that not all games have a competitive element (compare chess and solitaire); some, but not all, involve the amusement of children (catch, ring-a-ring-o’-roses); while some involve skill (tennis, chess) and others chance (dice). Our knowledge of the ‘meaning’ of the word game is therefore based not on some idealized notion of what a ‘game’ is, but on our ability to use the word in different contexts. Others would argue that a common ‘core’ meaning can be identified which is shared in all contexts (I know of no one who doesn’t think cups can contain liquids, for example), but that there is a significant amount of ‘fuzziness’ or semantic indeterminacy around that core. Indeterminacy is particularly evident with new lexemes, whose meanings are often contested.

EN

تصفح الموقع بالشكل العمودي