x
هدف البحث
بحث في العناوين
بحث في المحتوى
بحث في اسماء الكتب
بحث في اسماء المؤلفين
اختر القسم
موافق
Grammar
Tenses
Present
Present Simple
Present Continuous
Present Perfect
Present Perfect Continuous
Past
Past Continuous
Past Perfect
Past Perfect Continuous
Past Simple
Future
Future Simple
Future Continuous
Future Perfect
Future Perfect Continuous
Passive and Active
Parts Of Speech
Nouns
Countable and uncountable nouns
Verbal nouns
Singular and Plural nouns
Proper nouns
Nouns gender
Nouns definition
Concrete nouns
Abstract nouns
Common nouns
Collective nouns
Definition Of Nouns
Verbs
Stative and dynamic verbs
Finite and nonfinite verbs
To be verbs
Transitive and intransitive verbs
Auxiliary verbs
Modal verbs
Regular and irregular verbs
Action verbs
Adverbs
Relative adverbs
Interrogative adverbs
Adverbs of time
Adverbs of place
Adverbs of reason
Adverbs of quantity
Adverbs of manner
Adverbs of frequency
Adverbs of affirmation
Adjectives
Quantitative adjective
Proper adjective
Possessive adjective
Numeral adjective
Interrogative adjective
Distributive adjective
Descriptive adjective
Demonstrative adjective
Pronouns
Subject pronoun
Relative pronoun
Reflexive pronoun
Reciprocal pronoun
Possessive pronoun
Personal pronoun
Interrogative pronoun
Indefinite pronoun
Emphatic pronoun
Distributive pronoun
Demonstrative pronoun
Pre Position
Preposition by function
Time preposition
Reason preposition
Possession preposition
Place preposition
Phrases preposition
Origin preposition
Measure preposition
Direction preposition
Contrast preposition
Agent preposition
Preposition by construction
Simple preposition
Phrase preposition
Double preposition
Compound preposition
Conjunctions
Subordinating conjunction
Correlative conjunction
Coordinating conjunction
Conjunctive adverbs
Interjections
Express calling interjection
Grammar Rules
Preference
Requests and offers
wishes
Be used to
Some and any
Could have done
Describing people
Giving advices
Possession
Comparative and superlative
Giving Reason
Making Suggestions
Apologizing
Forming questions
Since and for
Directions
Obligation
Adverbials
invitation
Articles
Imaginary condition
Zero conditional
First conditional
Second conditional
Third conditional
Reported speech
Linguistics
Phonetics
Phonology
Semantics
Pragmatics
Linguistics fields
Syntax
Morphology
Semantics
pragmatics
History
Writing
Grammar
Reading Comprehension
Elementary
Intermediate
Advanced
The pragmatics of political interviews
المؤلف: David Hornsby
المصدر: Linguistics A complete introduction
الجزء والصفحة: 206-10
2023-12-27
303
The pragmatics of political interviews
The next time you hear a politician challenged to ‘answer the question’ in a television interview, you can be fairly sure that he/she is attempting to stretch the notion of ‘relevant’ beyond what the interviewer and audience are likely to find acceptable, by answering a different question to the one posed, and is being dragged back to observance of the maxim of relevance by the interviewer. In fact, the jousting match between a skilled interviewer and an experienced politician often amounts to an attempt by the former to force compliance with Grice’s maxims on the latter.
While the politician may have a strong interest in violating the maxims (for example by being obscure or ambiguous about unpopular policies), he/she is also aware of the strong countervailing pressure to observe them, and therefore often attempts to convince the audience of his/her intention to do so. When a politician prefaces remarks with ‘Let me be clear’, for example, it’s usually a sign that the maxim of manner is about to be violated. Many of the interviewer’s stock responses, on the other hand, can be interpreted as demanding of the interviewee that the maxims be observed:
‘But, Prime Minister, all the available evidence suggests this policy isn’t working…’ (quality) ‘
Your government does not seem to want to talk about unemployment’ (quantity)
‘I must press you to address the point the listener has made’ (relevance)
‘You haven’t been clear, have you, Prime Minister, about who will actually benefit from this proposal?’ (manner)
Politicians’ words are a matter of public record and are regularly tested for their honesty and consistency. As this famous exchange between Jeremy Paxman and ex-Home Secretary Michael Howard demonstrates, a politician would therefore rather violate manner by being obscure than run the risk of openly violating quality by being untruthful. Paxman actually asked the same question no fewer than 14 times before coining the word ‘obfuscommunication’, which we might define as ‘persistent and deliberate failure to observe the quantity maxim’.
Paxman: Did you threaten Derek Lewis?
Howard: I was not entitled to instruct Derek Lewis and I did not instruct him. And –
Paxman: Did you threaten to overrule him?
Howard: The truth of the matter is that Mr Marriott was not suspended. I did not –
Paxman: Did you threaten to overrule him?
Howard: I did not overrule Derek Lewis.
Paxman: Did you threaten to overrule him?
Howard: I took advice.
Paxman: You’re a master of obfuscommunication, Mr Howard.
A similar gap between entailment and implicature is evident in the logical and real-world use of numbers. Few people, for example, would argue with the statement ‘If both teams score two goals, the result is a draw’. Yet, when presented with the (unlikely) scoreline ‘West Ham United 6 Barcelona 2’, all English speakers agree that this is not a drawn game on the above definition, even though both teams have, quite clearly, scored two goals (one of them with four more to spare). The entailment of ‘two’ (‘at least two’) differs from the implicature (‘two and only two’) which flows from observance of the quantity maxim: we assume that, if the speaker had meant ‘at least two’, he/she would have said so and that in normal circumstances ‘two’ means ‘two and only two’.
An important property of implicatures is that, unlike entailments, they are defeasible, i.e. they can be cancelled:
Q: Did you give £50 to Children in Need?
A: Yes, in fact I gave £100.
?A: Yes, in fact I gave £49.
In the first reply, the implicature (‘£50 exactly’) is overridden by the ‘in fact…’ clause, but the entailment (‘at least £50’)
cannot be, so the second reply is pragmatically ill formed. The implicature that events follow the sequence in which they are uttered can be cancelled in a similar way:
I washed the floor, fed the cat, did the washing-up and watched TV, but not necessarily in that order.
Finally, Barry Blake (2008: 116) gives the example of Mr Brown meeting Mrs Jones for an illicit tryst at a hotel and being asked by the receptionist: ‘Are you married?’. Both reply, truthfully, that they are: the implicature ‘married to each other’ is one which neither party has an interest in cancelling!